Liability rules under evidentiary uncertainty, C Fluet

Tags: negligence, due care, contributory negligence, comparative negligence, standard of proof, liability rules, Journal of Law, Economics, imperfect information, legal concept, Rand Journal of Economics, Journal of Legal Studies, International Review of Law and Economics, decision rules, inadequate care, preponderance of evidence, injurer, care levels, pFu, Law and Economics, puF, Journal of Economics, liability rule, excessive care, error, strict liability rule, y0
Content: CIRPЙE Centre interuniversitaire sur le risque, les politiques йconomiques et l'emploi Cahier de recherche/working paper 06-06 Liability Rules under Evidentiary Uncertainty Claude Fluet Fйvrier/February 2006 _______________________ Fluet: Universitй du Quйbec а Montrйal and CIRPЙE (CP 8888 succ. Centre-Ville, Montrйal, Canada H3C 3P8 [email protected] An earlier version of this paper was presented at the EALE 20th Conference in Nancy. The Financial support of FQRSC and SSHRC is gratefully acknowledged.
Abstract: I consider the efficiency of liability rules when courts obtain imperfect information about precautionary behavior. I ask what tort rules are consistent with socially efficient precautions, what informational requirements the evidence about the parties' behavior must satisfy, what decision rules courts should apply when faced with imperfectly informative evidence, whether these decision rules can be formulated in terms of the legal concept of standard of proof, and whether some general characterization of the efficient standard can be given. I show that court judgments provide appropriate incentives to exert care if they signal that the party prevailing at trial most likely exerted due care, neither more nor less. Keywords: Tort, negligence, moral hazard, imperfect information, standard of proof JEL Classification: D8, K4
1 1 Introduction This paper considers the role of the legal concept of standard of proof in extending the economic model of tort law to situations where courts make errors in assessing care. The basic model without court error is well known to yield clear-cut predictions on how legal liability for accidents a¤ects precautionary behavior. When only unilateral care is involved, potential injurers are induced to take eў cient precautions under the strict liability rule or the negligence rule if courts set due care at the socially optimal level. With bilateral or joint-care, when potential victims as well as injurers a¤ect the risk of harm, the ...rst-best allocation of care is implemented under a variety of negligence-based rules, including simple negligence, negligence with the defense of contributory negligence, strict liability with the same defense, and comparative negligence.1 By contrast, no simple conclusion seems to emerge when the parties'behavior is imperfectly observable. The standard result is that the risk of court error may lead to either under or overcompliance with due care. If the courts' information is imperfect but not too noisy, a negligence rule would induce excessive precautions. In joint-care situations, equilibrium outcomes are said to be second-best under any liability rule. How the di¤erent rules compare would depend on the likelihood of victim versus injurer negligence, although it is also argued that court error is likely to matter less with comparative negligence. It has also been observed that courts could restore eў cient incentives by letting the legal standard of care di¤er from the socially eў cient level, but no general principle is o¤ered as to how they can proceed to do so.2 Ad hoc o¤setting adjustments in the legal standard of precautions are awkward considering that the interpretation of due care as socially eў cient care was a seminal assumption of the economic approach to tort law. Once this is discarded, it is not clear what the model has to say about actual tort rules. The trade-o¤ seems to be that, if the interpretation is maintained, negligence-based liability must lead to undesirable outcomes whenever courts may err in assessing care. This paper makes the point that such inconclusive results are unwarranted and stem from two shortcomings of the earlier 1The basic model is due to Brown (1973) and is developed in Landes and Posner (1987) and Shavell (1987). See also Kaplow and Shavell (2002) for a compact survey. 2See Diamond (1974), Calfee and Craswell (1984, 1986), Cooter and Ulen (1986, 2000), Shavell (1987), Kolstad, Ulen and Johnson (1990) and Edlin (1994).
2 literature on legal error. The ...rst is that court decisions were usually modeled as if courts were unaware that they possess imperfect information or attached no importance to the risk of error. This is surprising considering the importance in law, notably in common law, of concepts such as the standard of proof (the required weight of evidence) for court decisions. Another shortcoming is that the informational prerequisites for the provision of eў cient incentives under a negligence-based rule were not clearly speci...ed. Obviously, if the evidence about a party's behavior is very noisy, the ...nding of negligence must be uninformed and therefore cannot induce eў cient care. One would therefore want to characterize the informational conditions under which negligence-based rules are at all consistent with implementation of ...rst-best precautions. A related issue is the extent to which the informational requirements interact with the standard of proof. Similar questions have been tackled in a more recent strand of literature but from a di¤erent perspective focusing on the relation between legal error, litigation expenditures, incentives to sue, ex ante incentives to exert care, the social cost of legal error, etc.3 In this paper, I abstract from most of these considerations and revert to the issues raised in the earlier literature. I consider the basic model of liability rules and ask whether and under what conditions the eў cient precaution levels are implemented when courts obtain imperfect information about the parties' behavior. Speci...cally, I ask what tort rules are consistent with implementation of the ...rst best, what informational requirements the evidence about the parties'behavior must satisfy, what decision rules courts should apply when faced with imperfectly informative evidence, whether these decision rules can be formulated in terms of the legal concept of standard of proof, and whether some general characterization of the eў cient standard can be given. In this analysis, I assume that courts are unsure only about the parties'actual precautions, i.e., courts are able to determine the eў cient levels which they take as due care.4 I show that, if the risk of error is inevitable, eў cient care in the bilateral case can only be obtained with rules that take into consideration the precautionary behavior of both parties (e.g., strict liability with contributory 3See for instance Rubinfeld and Sappington (1987), Polinsky and Shavell (1989), Hylton (1990), Kaplow and Shavell (1994), Hay and Spier (1997), Sanchirico (1997), Bernardo, Talley and Welch (2000). 4The model is closely related to Fluet (1999) although that paper dealt with the negligence rule in unilateral care problems under limited liability constraints.
3
negligence is ineў cient). Regarding informational requirements, a necessary but not quite suў cient condition is that there be potential realizations of the evidence such that, following the occurrence of harm, eў cient care by both parties would appear most likely. Finally, with zero-one liability rules (i.e., rules where either the victim or the injurer bears 100 percent of the loss), the underlying standard of proof must be such that court rulings, viewed as signals, convey that the prevailing party barely exerted due care, neither more nor less. In other words, a decision in favor of a party must signal to outsiders that bare compliance with due care was the party's most likely action. I show that this implies a form of "preponderance of evidence"-- the standard of proof in common law for civil disputes-- in the sense that a claim is established only if it appears more likely than not to the court. Section 2 presents the framework. The main results are derived in section 3 for unilateral and bilateral care. Section 4 analyses the e¤ect of changes in the informational quality of the evidence, extends the analysis to comparative negligence, and discusses the extent to which punitive damages reduce informational requirements. Section 5 concludes.
2 The model
The starting point is the simple accident model with risk neutral agents and
zero litigation costs. An activity imposes a risk of loss L on third parties and
the only concern is the extent of precautions to reduce this risk-- exercising
the activity is taken as given. The probability of accident is p(u; v), a twice
di¤erentiable and strictly convex function with negative partial derivatives
pu and pv, where u, v 0 are the expenditures on precautions by injurer and victim respectively. The socially eў cient levels minimize p(u; v)L+u+v, the
sum of precaution and accident costs. Assuming an interior solution, they
satisfy
pu(u ; v )L = pv(u ; v )L = 1:
(1)
As noted, di¤erent liability rules implement eў cient care if courts can perfectly determine the parties'behavior and if legal standards of precaution are set at the socially eў cient levels. To illustrate, under "simple negligence" the injurer pays full compensatory damages to the victim if he is found negligent, irrespective of the victim's behavior. The expected cost facing a potential injurer is then U = p(u; v) (u)L + u where (u) = 1 if u < u and is zero otherwise; a potential victim's expected cost is V = p(u; v)[1 (u)]L+v.
4
Eў cient care is the Nash equilibrium, that is,
U (u ; v ) U (u; v ) and V (u ; v ) V (u ; v):
(2)
A single change is introduced. Rather than observing u and v, courts must rely on imperfectly informative evidence about the levels of care. The content of the evidence-- testimonies by witnesses, expert opinions, various documents-- is stochastic with probabilities that depend on the parties'care levels. Evidentiary outcomes are assumed to be comparable in terms of the "more favorable than" relation de...ned in Milgrom (1981), i.e., they can be ranked in terms of how damaging they are for the purpose of assessing a party's behavior. All relevant information can then be summarized by a random variable satisfying the monotone likelihood property-- an "index" conveying how relatively unfavorable the underlying multidimensional evidence turns out to be.5 The signals about u and v are denoted xe and ye respectively, with cumulative distributions F (x; u) and G(y; v) and corresponding density functions f (x; u) and g(y; v) assumed twice continuously di¤erentiable. Larger values correspond to more favorable evidence. The signals are independent for any levels of care and they take their values in the unit interval, which is without loss of generality since the range is arbitrary. This framework, with one additional condition, is summarized in the following assumptions. Assumption 1: For all u and v, f (x; u) > 0 and g(y; v) > 0 for x, y 2 [0; 1] and are zero otherwise. Assumption 2: For all u and v, fu(x; u)=f (x; u) and gv(y; v)=g(y; v) are strictly increasing in x and y respectively. The ...rst assumption means that error is inevitable because all possible realizations of the evidence are consistent with di¤erent levels of care. The second is the monotone likelihood ratio property (MLRP) and implies Fu, Gv < 0, except at the boundary of the support where the derivatives are nil. The third and last assumption is a convexity condition. Consider the event "accident occurs and xe < x " for some x 2 (0; 1). Its probability is p(u; v)F (u; x) and is strictly decreasing in u. Hence, the event represents 5Courts need not have direct access to the evidence. In an adversarial procedure, as evidence favors either the plainti¤ or the defendant, it will be submitted if submission costs are negligible and both parties have access to the same veri...able evidence (Milgrom and Roberts, 1986).
5 unfavorable information about the injurer's level of care, i.e., it is "bad news". I assume that, as the injurer exerts less care, the probability of bad news about his behavior increases at an increasing rate relative to the probability of accident itself. The same holds with respect to evidence concerning the victim. To write this formally, let u(p; v) and v(p; u) be obtained by inverting the probability of accident function p(u; v); that is, they represent a party's level of care as a function of the probability of accident, given the other party's care. Assumption 3: For x; y 2 (0; 1), pF [x; u(p; v)] and pG[y; v(p; u)] are strictly convex in p. The assumption implies that pF and pG are strictly convex in u and v respectively, ensuring that the parties' optimization problems are well behaved.6 Courts are able to perfectly assess damages and the extent of the risk as a function of care. As in the basic accident model, they can therefore determine the eў cient levels of precaution, which they take as due care. However, courts do not observe the true levels of care. They obtain evidence which they know to be imperfect and from which they draw likelihood assessments. On this basis, and given the tort rule that applies, they assign liability. When the rule requires a decision concerning a party's negligence, courts weigh whether the evidence about a party's behavior is suў ciently unfavorable. This amounts to using critical values x and y such that the injurer is found negligent if xe < x and the victim is found negligent if ye < y. The evidentiary thresholds x and y reect the courts' standard of proof. Lower thresholds mean that for ...nding negligence courts need more convincing evidence that care was insuў cient. The parties know the court's decision rule and therefore anticipate the probability of being found negligent as a function of their level of care. 6Assumption 1 is known as invariant support. Assumption 3 is in lieu of the Convexity of the distribution function Condition. Given puu > 0, Fu < 0, @u(p; v)[email protected] < 0, it implies @2p(u; v)F (u; x)[email protected] = [@pF (x; u(p; v))[email protected]] puu + @2pF (x; u(p; v))[email protected] (pu)2 > 0:
6
3 Main results It is useful to discuss ...rst the case where the occurrence of harm depends only on the potential injurer's behavior. The relation between evidentiary thresholds and incentives to exert care is then straightforward. The properties extend to joint care.
Unilateral care
When only the injurer's precautions matter, the probability of accident is
p(u) with p0 < 0 and p00 > 0. Socially eў cient care minimizes p(u)L + u,
satisfying
p0(u )L = 1:
(3)
Strict liability induces eў cient precautions. The issue is whether this is also feasible with the negligence rule. If x is the threshold for ...nding negligence, a potential injurer minimizes the expected cost p(u)F (x; u)L + u. The equilibrium level of care satis...es the ...rst-order condition7
[p0(u)F (x; u) + p(u)Fu(x; u)] L = 1:
(4)
Comparing with (3), u is a solution if x = 1 since in that case F = 1 and Fu = 0, but this corresponds to the strict liability rule. The negligence rule requires that an injurer exerting due care avoids liability with positive probability, i.e., u must be a solution for some x < 1. Substituting from (3) in (4) and setting care at the socially optimal level, the eў cient threshold solves
'(x) := [p0(u )F (x; u ) + p(u )Fu(x; u )] = p0(u ):
(5)
'(x) is the change in the probability of being found negligent when care varies marginally from the eў cient level, given the evidentiary threshold. Condition (5) therefore requires that, when the injurer exerts due care, a marginal change in the level of care has the same e¤ect on the probability of being found negligent as it has on the probability of accident.
­Figure 1 about here ­ 7The second-order condition is satis...ed by assumption 3.
7
Obviously, '(0) = 0 and '(1) = p0(u ). In ...gure 1, ' is drawn as a function of F (x; u ), a positive monotonic transformation of x. Taking the ...rst and second-order derivatives,
d'(x) =
p0(u ) + p(u ) fu(x; u ) ;
(6)
dF (x; u )
f (x; u )
d2'(x) dF (x; u )2 =
p(u ) d fu(x; u ) < 0; f (x; u ) dx f (x; u )
(7)
where the inequality follows from MLRP. Hence, the curve is strictly concave. The eў cient evidentiary threshold is denoted xb. F (xb; u ) is the probability that an injurer exerting due care is erroneously found negligent and will be referred to as the type 1 error. There are two requirements for the socially eў cient precautions to be implemented with a negligence rule. First, the relevant curves must intersect, i.e., there must exist xb < 1 as de...ned. This depends on how informative the evidence is likely to be with respect to the injurer's behavior. As discussed in section 4, insuў ciently informative evidence entails a curve such as a in the ...gure. That curve remains below the horizontal line drawn from p0(u ) except at the upper bound of the support. The consequence is that providing the desired incentives can then only be obtained with the strict liability rule. Assuming the evidence is suў ciently informative, the second requirement is that courts use the appropriate evidentiary threshold. This has to do with the standard of proof for establishing negligence. Before discussing the standard, I give a condition ensuring that the evidence is suў ciently informative. Condition 1: u maximizes p(u)f (x0; u) for some x0 < 1. The expression p(u)f (x; u) is the probability that harm occurs together with the realized evidence being x, conditional on the level of care. In statistical terminology, it is the likelihood of the unknown care level u, given the "data"which comprise the occurrence of harm and the evidence x. Condition 1 requires that, for some realization of the evidence, due care is the most likely level of care. When the court is presented with x0, its "maximum likelihood estimate"of the injurer's care is precisely u . Note the di¤erence with a Bayesian formulation. If priors about u are described by the density (u) and posteriors by (u j x), then by Bayes'rule
8
the relative posterior probability of u versus u0 is
(u j x) p(u)f (x; u) (u) (u0 j x) = p(u0)f (x; u0) (u0) ;
where the term in brackets is the likelihood ratio of u versus u0 given the "data". In what follows, court decision-making disregards priors about the injurer's conduct and is solely in terms of relative likelihood. This captures the idea that the court's decision rests only on the "particular facts" whose probability depends on what the defendant might have done. The issue of priors is discussed further in section 5. From the necessary condition for a maximum in condition 1, x0 solves
p0(u
)
=
fu(x; u
) :
(8)
p(u ) f (x; u )
The right-hand side is strictly increasing in x, hence x0 is unique.8 The critical x0 has another interpretation as well. Recalling (6) and (7), '(x) reaches a strict interior maximum at x0 as represented in ...gure 1. The next result follows immediately. Lemma 1: Under condition 1, there is a unique xb < x0 such that '(xb) = p0(u ). '(x) is increasing if x < x0, decreasing if x > x0. A threshold x0 < xb leads to underprecaution, a threshold x00 2 (xb; 1) to overprecaution. A threshold lower than the eў cient xb corresponds to a higher standard of proof than would be required to provide eў cient incentives. Conversely, a less demanding standard of proof provides too much incentives.9 Lemma 2: If x 7 x0, then arg maxu p(u)f (x; u) 7 u . Proof: See Appendix. Lemma 2 partitions possible realizations of the evidence in terms of whether inadequate (u < u ) or suў cient care (u u ) is most likely. Its interpretive role is discussed after the next proposition.
8As a function of x, fu=f increases from negative to positive. It needs to become suў ciently large for there to exist x0 as de...ned. Loosely speaking, poor information corresponds to a at fu=f function. 9In the limit, as x00 tends to unity, the negligence rule becomes indistinguishable from strict liability. A threshold greater than x0 can be interpreted as putting on the injurer the "burden of persuasion" (see footnote 18).
9 Proposition 1: If xb is the eў cient evidentiary threshold for negligence in the unilateral case, then arg maxu p(u)f (x; u) < u for all x < xb. Moreover, xb is eў cient if and only if u maximizes p(u) (1 F (xb; u)). Proof: See Appendix. The court ...nds negligence only if x < xb, when the most likely level of care is below due care. The underlying standard of proof therefore entails a form of "preponderance of evidence", i.e., negligence is deemed proved only if inadequate care is more likely than due care given the evidence at trial. However, the condition is not suў cient. By lemma 2, for any x 2 [xb; x0), inadequate care is also more likely than due care but the defendant is nevertheless not found negligent. The interpretation is therefore that, to establish negligence, inadequate care must be suў ciently more likely than due care, i.e., there must be a suў cient "preponderance of evidence". How much so is characterized in the second part of proposition 1. The characterization is in terms of court rulings viewed as signals about defendants'behavior. I now consider the case of outsiders who understand the situation and the courts' decision rule, but do not have access to the detailed evidence presented at trial. What should they infer about a defendant's likely level of care when the court decides in his favor? For instance, in a criminal trial guilt must be proved beyond a reasonable doubt, hence acquittal need not be a strong signal that the accused is innocent. A much lower standard of proof-- preponderance of evidence-- is used for civil trials in common law. A decision in favor of the defendant is then a stronger signal that he exerted due care. One way to approach these questions is to ask what estimate outsiders would form of the injurer's care, upon knowing only that harm occurred and that the injurer was found non negligent. As a function of the care level, the probability of this event is p(u)(1 F (xb; u)). Borrowing from statistical terminology once more, the expression is the likelihood of the unknown u given that harm occurred and that the defendant escaped liability. Thus, the second part of the proposition states that, from the outsiders'point of view, the most likely level of care, when the injurer prevails, is due care, i.e., u is the outsiders' maximum likelihood estimate of the injurer's care. Noting that arg max p(u)[1 F (x; u)] u is increasing in x, the interpretation is therefore that the courts'underlying
10 standard of proof should not be weak to the point that a defendant escaping liability suggests more than due care-- as would be the case with a threshold to the right of xb. Neither should the standard be stringent to the point that escaping liability suggests less than due care, as would follow from a threshold to the left of xb. Observe also that p(u)(1 F (xb; u)) is the probability that victims will bear a loss, as a function of the injurer's care level. Therefore, the evidentiary threshold is eў cient if any deviation from due care by the injurer bene...ts potential victims. This generalizes a property of the negligence rule when care is observable without error.10 To conclude the section, I relate the results to the existing literature. The most common approach has been to assume that courts observe a signal xe = u + e", where e" is an error term, and that they ...nd negligence if xe < u . Several authors (e.g., Shavell, 1987, Kolstad et al., 1990) have noted that this induces insuў cient care if the variance of e" is large and excessive care if it is small. By itself, xe = u + e" is consistent with and is in fact a particular case of the present model provided xe satis...es MLRP.11 However, two points were made. First, if the evidence is suў ciently poor (e.g., if the variance of e" is large), there may be no threshold for negligence that induces eў cient care. Secondly, as an evidentiary threshold, u is perfectly arbitrary. To see this, observe that the rule "...nd negligence if xe < u " takes no account of how informative xe is. Furthermore, it disregards part of the relevant evidence, namely the information from the occurrence of harm itself. To take an extreme case, suppose care can be either low or high with, say, ul = 0 and uh = 1. Suppose further that pl = 0:99 while ph = 0:01. The mere occurrence of harm then constitutes rather strong evidence that care was low. For a decision in favor of the injurer to convey that high care is at least as likely as low care, the threshold for xe needs to be higher than u . Proposition 1 nevertheless suggests that the common law standard of proof may be too weak. According to the usual interpretation, a claim is 10Using the notation of section 2, the probability of loss by victims is then p(u)[1 (u)]. This is zero if u < u and it equals p(u) if u u . Hence, it is maximized at u = u . 11Let H(") be the cumulative distribution function of e" with density h("). Then F (x; u) = H(x u) and MLRP is satis...ed if (h0)2 hh00 > 0. With this speci...cation, one would want to discard the convention that xe takes its values in the unit interval. Alternatively, the signal ze := H(xe u1) could be introduced where u1 > 0 is an arbitrary ...xed level of care. ze 2 [0; 1] then conveys the same information as xe and it satis...es MLRP if xe does.
11 established by a "preponderance of evidence"if it is shown to be more likely true than not true.12 Negligence would therefore be found whenever inadequate care is more likely than due care. By lemma 2, this amounts to using x0 as evidentiary threshold, resulting in overcompliance. The issue of excessive care has been much debated in malpractice liability. A common argument is that incentives to practice medicine defensively are increased by the possibility of court error, given that precautionary behavior is particularly diў cult to verify ex post.13 The above suggests that excessive care results not so much from the risk of court error per se as from too weak a standard of proof. Bilateral care When both injurer and victim can take precautions, the eў cient levels minimize p(u; v)L + u + v and satisfy the ...rst-order conditions (1). Liability rules for joint care belong to two categories. One class of rules assigns liability on the basis of the behavior of only one party. This includes "simple negligence", where only the injurer's behavior is taken into account, and "strict liability with the defense of contributory negligence"where only the victim's behavior is considered. In the other class of rules, the behavior of both parties is taken into account, as in "negligence with the defense of contributory negligence"and "comparative negligence". Rules in the ...rst category are ineў cient if behavior is imperfectly observable. Consider the simple negligence rule. With the threshold x, u and v constitute a Nash equilibrium if u minimizes p(u; v )F (x; u)L + u and v minimizes p(u ; v)[1 F (x; u )]L + v. The eў cient v solves the second problem only if F (x; u ) = 0. By assumption 1, this implies F (x; u) = 0 for all u. Hence, the injurer has no incentive to take care and u cannot be part of the equilibrium. A similar argument applies to strict liability with the defense of contributory negligence.14 Proposition 2: With bilateral care, the rules of negligence and of strict liability with the defense of contributory negligence are inconsistent with the ...rst-best allocation of care. 12"A bare preponderance is suў cient, though the scales drop but a feather's weight" (Livanovitch vs Livanovitch, 99Vt. 327 131A. 799, 1926). 13The debate is surveyed in Kessler and McClellan (1995) who present evidence of excess precautions. 14This is true if "punitive damages" are ruled out. These are discussed in section 4.
12
The point is that, so long as courts may err in determining care, there are no evidentiary thresholds under the above rules that implement the eў cient precautions as a noncooperative equilibrium. Among the second class of tort rules, the traditional one in common law is negligence with the defense of contributory negligence, "contributory negligence"hereafter.15 The injurer is then liable for the victim's loss if he is found negligent and the victim is not found negligent. With the thresholds x and y for injurer and victim, the injurer is therefore liable only if the evidence satis...es xe < x and ye y. The injurer's expected cost is then
U = p(u; v)F (x; u) (1 G(y; v)) L + u;
while that of the victim is
V = p(u; v) [1 F (x; u) (1 G(y; v))] L + v.
At a Nash equilibrium with positive care levels, u and v satisfy the ...rstorder conditions16:
[pu(u; v)F (x; u) + p(u; v)Fu(x; u)] (1 G(y; v)) L = 1; fpv(u; v) [1 F (x; u)(1 G(y; v))] + p(u; v)F (x; u)Gv(y; v)g L = 1: Setting care at the eў cient levels and substituting from (1), the eў cient thresholds xb and yb solve:
[pu(u ; v )F (x; u )+p(u ; v )Fu(x; u )] (1 G(y; v )) = pu(u ; v ); (9)
[pv(u ; v )G(y; v ) + p(u ; v )Gv(y; v )] = pv(u ; v ):
(10)
The last condition has the same form as (5) in the preceding section. Thus, y = 1 is a solution but clearly only y < 1 is consistent with (9). In the ...gures 2 and 3, all functions are evaluated at the eў cient care levels. The eў cient thresholds are shown in terms of the type 1 errors = F (xb; u )
15Interchanging the role of the parties, what follows also applies to the theoretical rule of "dual contributory negligence" de...ned in Brown (1973). Under this rule the injurer is always liable except when the victim is found negligent and the injurer nonnegligent. Comparative negligence is considered in section 4. 16The conditions for an equilibrium are the same as in (2), but with the parties'expected cost U and V de...ned as above. By assumption 3 these functions are strictly convex in u and v respectively.
13
and = G(yb; v ). I introduce a condition which parallels condition 1 for unilateral care. Condition 2: For some x0, y0 < 1, (u ; v ) = arg max p(u; v)g(y0; v)f (x0; u): u;v Again, the expression is the likelihood of the pair of care levels (u; v) given the occurrence of harm and the evidence x0 and y0. The condition requires that there be realizations of the evidence for which due care by both parties is most likely.
­Figures 2 and 3 about here ­
Extending previous results, condition 2 implies the existence of yb < y0 solving (10). However, the condition is not suў cient with respect to the injurer as there is an asymmetry in the determination of the eў cient thresholds. The one concerning the victim is obtained directly from (10) independently of the injurer's threshold, but the latter depends on the type 1 error with respect to the victim.
Lemma 3: Under condition 2, there exists yb < y0 solving (10); there exists xb x0 solving (9) if
[pu(u ; v )F (x0; u ) + p(u ; v )Fu(x0; u )]
1
pu(u ; v G(yb; v
) ):
If the above inequality is strict, there are in fact two solutions to (9), as shown in ...gure 3. I retain only the one corresponding to the smallest type 1 error.17 As discussed below, this is appropriate if the victim bears the burden of persuasion regarding the injurer's negligence and if the standard of proof involves a form of "preponderance of evidence". The following is the analog to proposition 1. Proposition 3: xb and yb are eў cient evidentiary thresholds under contributory negligence if and only if
u = arg max p(u; v ) [1 F (xb; u) (1 G(yb; v ))] ;
(11)
u
v = arg max p(u ; v) (1 G(yb; v)) F (xb; u ):
(12)
v
17 In the ...gures, 0 = F (x0; u ) and 0 = G(y0; v ). The solutions and 0 to (9) satisfy < 0 < 0.
14 arg maxv p(u ; v)g(y; v) < v if y < yb, arg maxu p(u; v )f (x; u) < u if x < xb with xb x0. Proof: See Appendix. As in the unilateral case, negligence is found only if inadequate care is more likely than due care. This is consistent with the injurer bearing the burden of proving the victim's negligence, by a suў cient preponderance of evidence, in order to bene...t from the defense of contributory negligence. It is also consistent with the victim bearing the burden of proving the injurer's negligence, provided we choose the solution xb x0 to condition (9) rather than the one corresponding to 0 in ...gure 3. With the latter, it would be as if the injurer had the burden of proving that he was not negligent.18 Consider now the interpretation of court decisions as signals about the parties' behavior. The expression in (11) is the likelihood of the injurer's care level u upon knowing that harm occurred and that the injurer won the trial. A suit won by the injurer must convey that he barely undertook due care, neither more nor less. The maximum likelihood u takes into account the fact that the injurer avoids liability if found non-negligent or if the victim is found negligent. The expression in (12) is the likelihood of the victim's care level v given that the victim won the case. The maximum likelihood v is then the same as would be obtained by asking what level of care is most likely, given that the victim was not found negligent. The result implies that courts should apply a weaker standard of proof for ...nding injurer negligence than for victim negligence. Indeed, at the eў cient threshold19, arg max p(u; v ) [1 F (xb; u)] > u : u The outsiders' maximum likelihood u, upon learning that the injurer was found non-negligent (and not simply that he won the case), is greater than due care. Intuitively, a ruling of non negligence with respect to the injurer represents more favorable information about the injurer's behavior than a 18 Let 0 = F (x0; u ) so that x0 > x0. With the threshold x0, the injurer avoids being found negligent only if x x0. By lemma 2, this implies arg maxu p(u; v )f (x; u) u , i.e., a ...nding of negligence is avoided only if suў cient care appears most likely. To keep the exposition simple, I henceforth disregard this possible allocation of the burden of persuasion. 19By proposition 3, u maximizes p(1 F ) + GpF . Since pF is decreasing in u, it must be that p(1 F ) is increasing at u .
15 similar ruling about the victim. Accordingly, it must be that courts require less convincing evidence to ...nd an injurer negligent. Finally, observe that the expression in (11) is the probability that the victim bears a loss, as a function of the injurer's precautions and assuming the victim undertook due care. A potential victim bene...ts from any deviation by the injurer from his eў cient care level. Similarly, the right-hand side of (12) is the probability that the injurer will have to pay damages. Any deviation by the victim from his eў cient care level bene...ts potential injurers. Thus, under the eў cient thresholds, the liability rule exhibits a "saddle point" property. Schweizer (2005) has shown that this property is shared by eў cient liability rules in many di¤erent contexts. 4 Extensions Information Inducing eў cient precautions is feasible only with suў ciently informative evidence. I now discuss the e¤ect of changes in the quality of the evidence. Intuitively, more informative evidence should reduce the risk of error. Consider two situations di¤ering only in the quality of the evidence about the injurer's behavior. One is characterized by F (x; u), the other by the distribution H(x; u) also satisfying assumptions 1 to 3. A general criterion for ranking information structures is the following. Definition: H is more informative than F with respect to u if, for all u, Hu(x1; u) < Fu(x2; u) for x1; x2 2 (0; 1) such that F (x1; u) = H(x2; u). The more informative the evidence, the more the probability of unfavorable evidence is sensitive to changes in the level of care. The condition is equivalent to other well known criteria.20 To see the implications, consider again the negligence rule in the case of unilateral care. Choose the evidentiary thresholds so that the type 1 error is the same in both situations, i.e., F (x1; u ) = H(x2; u ). Then, if H is more informative than F , [p0(u )H(x2; u )+p(u )Hu(x2; u )] > [p0(u )F (x1; u )+p(u )Fu(x1; u )] : 20Demougin and Fluet (2001) show the equivalence with Kim's (1995) criterion de...ned in terms of mean preserving spreads of the likelihood ratio fu=f .
16 Marginal incentives are greater with H and this is true for any pair of thresholds with the same type 1 error. In ...gure 1, the '-curve for H is therefore above the one for F , for example curve b. Conversely, if H were less informative, the curve would be below the one for F . A particular case is curve a where implementing the eў cient level of care is no longer feasible under a negligence rule.21 Otherwise, the less informative the evidence, the greater the type 1 error under the eў cient standard of proof. This bene...ts potential victims since injurers are held liable more often. Similar results obtain under joint care with the rule of contributory negligence. In the ...gures 2 and 3, less informative evidence shifts the incentive curves downward. With suў ciently poorer evidence about either the victim or the injurer, at least one set of curves will not intersect and the ...rst best will no longer be feasible. The e¤ect on court error is similarly straightforward. Less informative evidence about the victim's behavior leads to a higher type 1 error . In turn, this induces a downward shift in the relevant curve of ...gure 3, yielding an increase in the type 1 error as well. The redistributive e¤ects on the parties'well-being is not a priori obvious, but I show below that the change is bene...cial to potential victims (i.e., increases more than ). Finally, less informative evidence about the injurer's behavior only a¤ects the curve in ...gure 3 and is obviously bene...cial to victims. Proposition 4: Under contributory negligence with the eў cient standards of proof, potential victims bene...t from poorer evidence about either the victims'or the injurers'precautions. (i) Poorer evidence about the victim's care increases the type 1 errors for both victim and injurer; (ii) poorer evidence about the injurer's care increases the injurer type 1 error with no e¤ect on victim type 1 error. Proof: See Appendix. When courts obtain perfect information about the parties'behavior, victims bear 100 per cent of expected accident costs under contributory negligence. The possibility of error shifts part of these costs to injurers. It should be emphasized that the informational quality of the evidence a¤ects the risk of erroneously ...nding negligence, although the underlying standard of proof 21In particular, condition 1 is then not satis...ed. Thus, the conditions 1 and 2 refer to how informative the evidence is.
17
is invariant and satis...es the conditions of proposition 3. Irrespective of the quality of the evidence, a ruling in favor of a party signals that bare compliance with due care is most likely. Given the standard of proof, the type 1 errors then follow from the quality of the evidence.
Comparative negligence
Between the mid 1960s and early 1980s, most US jurisdictions replaced the principle of contributory negligence with comparative negligence. The latter di¤ers by apportioning the loss between injurer and victim when both parties are found negligent, which is seen as less harsh than the complete bar to recovery by a negligent victim under contributory negligence.22 Comparative or relative negligence is also the main liability rule in England and in civil law countries. I consider a simple form where the victim bears a given fraction of the loss when both parties are found negligent.23 With the evidentiary thresholds x and y, the injurer is liable for the whole loss if xe < x and ye y and for a fraction 1 if xe < x and ye < y. The injurer's expected cost is
U = p(u; v)F (x; u) [1 G(y; v) + (1 )G(y; v)] = p(u; v)F (x; u) (1 G(y; v)) L + u
and the victim's is
V = p(u; v) [1 F (x; u) (1 G(y; v))] L + v:
Proceeding as before, the eў cient thresholds x0 and y0 solve
[pu(u ; v )F (x; u )+p(u ; v )Fu(x; u )] (1 G(y; v )) = pu(u ; v ); (13)
[pv(u ; v )G(y; v )+p(u ; v )Gv(y; v )] = pv(u ; v ):
(14)
Again there may be several solutions but I retain only the ones with the smallest type 1 errors.24
22The "fairness"argument played an important role in the spread of comparative negligence. See Landes and Posner (1987), but also Curran (1992) who argues that the adoption of strict product liability in the 1960s reduced manufacturers'opposition to comparative negligence. 23There are many variants of comparative negligence. Actual rules usually apportion the loss in proportion to the parties'degree of negligence. 24 That is, x0 < x0 and y0 < y0.
18 Comparing (14) and (10), it is readily seen that < 1 amounts to a proportional downward shift in the incentive curve of ...gure 2. Hence, we must have y0 > yb, where the latter is the eў cient threshold under contributory negligence. Since the injurer now sometimes shares part of the loss, the standard of proof for victim negligence must be less demanding in order to provide potential victims with the appropriate incentives. Comparing (13) and (9), the implications regarding the injurer's threshold are at ...rst sight ambiguous: < 1 increases the injurers' incentives but a larger y reduces them. Proposition 5: Let xb and yb be the eў cient thresholds under contributory negligence, x0 and y0 the eў cient thresholds under comparative negligence. Then x0 > xb, y0 > yb and potential victims are better o¤ under comparative negligence than under contributory negligence. Proof: See Appendix. The standard of proof for ...nding negligence must now be weaker for both parties, although inadequate care is still required to be more likely than due care. Victims are found negligent more often but nevertheless face a lower expected cost than under contributory negligence.25 Thus, the switch to comparative negligence may indeed bene...t victims while still maintaining eў cient incentives. Proposition 5 also shows that comparative negligence does not improve things regarding the feasibility of implementing the ...rst best compared to contributory negligence. If the ...rst best is feasible with some < 1, it is also feasible with = 1 but the converse does not hold. When the evidence about the parties' behavior is poor, contributory negligence may therefore be the better rule since comparative negligence dilutes incentives.26 On the other hand, if common law courts apply too weak a standard of proof (corresponding, say, to the thresholds x0 and y0) and if the evidence is relatively informative, comparative negligence may well yield less distortion from the ...rst best.27 25Similar results were found by Edlin (1994), but with the interpretation that due care standards should be set higher under comparative negligence. 26There is evidence that the switch to comparative negligence from contributory negligence has resulted in reduced incentives to exert care (e.g., White, 1989, and Flanagan et al., 1989). 27This is reminiscent of the claim by Cooter and Ulen (1986) and Edlin (1994) that comparative negligence would generally fare better.
19
Punitive damages Punitive in addition to compensatory damages are sometimes awarded, usually because the defendant's conduct has been particularly reprehensible. The economics literature has stressed the deterrence rationale for situations where an injurer may escape liability for the harm he caused, e.g., because he cannot always be identi...ed.28 I briey examine the extent to which punitive damages reduce informational requirements in the joint care problem. From the principal-agent literature, it is well known that suў ciently large money incentives solve the moral hazard problem when the agent is risk neutral, even though information is poor. In the bilateral care situation, one therefore expects that appropriate punitive damages can always induce injurers to undertake eў cient precautions. I examine whether, under contributory negligence, the fear of not being paid punitive damages (assuming these do not go to the state) might also induce potential victims to exert care, even though the evidence about their behavior is poor. I show that the answer is negative, i.e., the prospect of more than compensatory damages has no e¤ect on informational requirements with respect to the victim nor on the standard of proof for deciding victim negligence. Let D L be the total damages awarded (the punitive part is then D L) under the contributory negligence rule with evidentiary threshold x and y. The injurer's expected cost is
U = p(u; v)F (x; u) (1 G(y; v)) D + u
(15)
and the victim's is
V = p(u; v) [L F (x; u) (1 G(y; v)) D] + v.
(16)
The victim bears the loss L but is paid D when he wins the case. Obviously, x > 0 is needed to provide the injurer with incentives. From (16), it follows that v is the best reply to u if the victim's threshold satis...es
@p(u ; v) (1 G(yb; v))
= 0:
@v
v=v
This is the same condition as in proposition 3. Informational requirements concerning the victim are therefore not improved and the standard of proof
28 See for instance Polinsky and Shavell (1998).
20
is the same as before. Given yb, it is clear from (15) that u can be made to be the best reply to v with di¤erent combinations of x and D. One possibility is to disregard the injurer's conduct altogether and to set x = 1 with the damage multiplier equal to
D= L1
1 G(yb; v
; )
i.e., the reciprocal of the probability that the injurer avoids liability due to the victim being found negligent. Overall, except for the punitive part, the rule corresponds to strict liability with the defense of contributory negligence. The implication is that information about the injurer's conduct is not needed with appropriate punitive damages, although the need to obtain suў ciently informative evidence about the victim's care remains unchanged. The next proposition summarizes the results. Proposition 6: Appropriate punitive damages implement the eў cient levels of care, provided the threshold yb for victim negligence satis...es v = arg maxv p(u ; v) (1 G(yb; v)).
5 Concluding remarks A simplifying assumption of the foregoing analysis is that veri...able information about precautionary behavior is exogenously made available to the parties and can be communicated to the court at negligible cost. Within the limits of this assumption, the basic economic model of liability rules easily extends to imperfect information about care. When the situation involves bilateral precautions, eў cient care is implemented through negligence-based rules assigning liability on the basis of both parties'behavior, provided the evidence is suў ciently informative and courts use the appropriate standard of proof. In all-or-nothing rules such as negligence with the defense of contributory negligence, the underlying standard of proof is eў cient if the outcome of a trial conveys that the prevailing party most likely exerted neither more nor less than due care. In rules which involve sharing the loss such as comparative negligence, the eў cient standards of proof are weaker and both the plainti¤ and defendant will be found negligent more often. In all cases, eў ciency requires that a claim is proved only if it appears more likely than not by some margin.
21
In this analysis, court decisions rest on the relative likelihood of negligent behavior versus due care. Relative likelihood is meant in the usual mathematical sense. Speci...cally, courts do not use Bayesian inference to update priors about how parties generally behave. It has been noted by several authors that the courts'decision process in this respect is typically not Bayesian and that there are eў ciency-based rationales (i.e., the provision of incentives) for rules of evidence and rules of proof-- e.g., Posner (1999), Daughety and Reinganum (2000a, 2000b), Fluet (2003), Demougin and Fluet (2006). In the above framework, this means that courts disregard any understanding they may have of equilibrium behavior and base their decisions on the weight of evidence about the parties'actions.
Appendix
Proof of lemma 2: I ...rst show that arg maxu p(u)f (x; u) is non decreasing in x. Let p(u0)f (x0; u0) p(u)f (x0; u) for all u. Then, for u < u0 and x > x0,
p(u) f (x0; u0) f (x; u0)
p(u0)
f (x0; u)
<
; f (x; u)
where the strict inequality follows from MLRP (i.e., f (x; u0)=f (x; u) is strictly increasing in x if u0 > u). Hence u maximizes the likelihood at x > x0 only if u u0. I now show that the latter inequality is strict, focusing on the case u0 = u . By lemma 1 '0(x) ? 0 if x 7 x0. Now,
@[p(u)f (x; u)][email protected]=u = p0(u )f (x; u ) + p(u )fu(x; u ) = '0(x):
Hence, for x > x0 there is u > u with strictly greater likelihood than u , implying arg maxu p(u)f (x; u) > u . A similar argument shows that arg maxu p(u)f (x; u) < u for x < x0. Proof of proposition 1: The ...rst claim follows directly from the lemmas. Concerning the second, the necessary condition for a maximum is
@p (1 F ) = p0 (1 @u
F)
pFu = 0:
(17)
If the maximum is at u for the given xb, condition (5) holds and suў ciency is proved. Necessity follows if
@2p (1 @u2
F)
= p00(1
F)
2p0Fu
pFuu < 0
22
whenever (17) holds, i.e., if p (1
from (17),
@2p (1 F )
@u2
=
By assumption 3,
F ) is pseudo-concave in u. Substituting
p00p p0
2p0 Fu
pFuu:
@2pF
1
@p2 = (p0)2
2p0
p00p p0 Fu + pFuu > 0:
(18)
Hence, @2p (1 F ) [email protected] < 0 at a stationary point, which is therefore a global maximum.
Proof of proposition 3: The proof is similar to that of proposition 1. I only show the necessity of condition (11). The ...rst-order condition for a maximum is
@p[1 F (1 G)]
@u
= pu (puF + pFu) (1 G) = 0:
(19)
It remains to show that u satisfying (19) is a global maximum. This follows if p[1 F (1 G)] is pseudo-concave in u, i.e., if for any solution satisfying (19)
@2p[1 F (1 G)]
@u2
= puu (puuF + 2 puFu + pFuu) (1 G)
= puu
puuF + 2 puFu + pFuu puF + pFu
pu < 0;
(20)
where the second expression is obtained by substituting from (19). The inequality (20) is equivalent to
2pu
puup pu
Fu + pFuu > 0;
which follows from assumption 3 (see (18) in the proof of proposition 1).
Proof of proposition 4: The claims (i) and (ii) and the statement that
poorer evidence about injurers bene...ts victims follow from the discussion. I
prove that victims also bene...t from poorer evidence about their own precau-
tions. A less informative G implies an increase in the type 1 error . From
(9),
dxb =
puF + pFu
>0
d (1 )(puf + pfu)
23
where the denominator is negative for xb < x0. The e¤ect on injurers' expected liability costs is
dpF (1 d
) = pF + p(1 )f dxb d = p2 f Fu F fu > 0; puf + pfu
where the numerator is negative by MLRP. Proof of proposition 5: y0 > yb is obvious from (14) given < 1. x0 > xb follows from (13) if G(y0; v ) is decreasing in . From (14),
d G(y0; v )
dy0
= G+ g
d
d
= gvG gGv p < 0:
(21)
pvg + pgv
The numerator is positive by MLRP and the denominator negative since y0 < y0. Potential victims are better o¤ under comparative negligence if p[1 F (1 G)] is increasing in . Now,
dF (1 G)
dx0 d G
= (1 G)f
F:
(22)
d
d
d
From (13),
dx0 = d (1
Substituting in (22),
puF + pFu
dG :
G)(puf + pfu) d
dF (1
G] =p
f Fu
fuF
dG < 0:
d
puf + pfu d
The sign follows from (21), MLRP and puf + pfu < 0 for x0 < x0.
References Bernardo, A., E. Talley and I. Welch (2000), "A theory of legal presumptions", Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 16, 1-49.
24 Brown, J. P. (1973), "Toward an economic theory of liability", Journal of Legal Studies 2, 323-349. Cooter, R. and T. Ulen (1986), "An economic case for comparative negligence", New York University Law Review 61, 1067-1110. Cooter, R. and T. Ulen (2000), Law and Economics, 3rd ed., Addison Wesley Longman, Reading (Mass.). Calfee, J. et R. Craswell (1984), "Some e¤ects of uncertainty on compliance with legal standards", Virginia Law Review 70, 965-1003. Craswell, R. and J. E. Calfee (1986), "Deterrence and uncertain legal standards", Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 2, 279-303. Curran, C. (1992), "The spread of the comparative negligence rule in the Un ited States", International Review of Law and Economics 12, 317-332. Daughety, A. F. and J. F. Reinganum (2000a), "Appealing judgments", Rand Journal of Economics 31, 502-526. Daughety, A. F. and J. F. Reinganum (2000b), "On the economics of trial: adversarial process, eidence, and equilibrium bias", Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 16, 365-394. Demougin, D. and C. Fluet (2001), "Ranking of information systems in agency models: an integral condition", Economic Theory 17(2), 489496. Demougin, D. and C. Fluet (2006), "Preponderance of evidence", European Economic Review, forthcoming. Diamond, P. (1974), "Single activity accidents", Bell Journal of Economics 5, 366-405. Edlin, A. (1994), "Eў cient standards of due care: should courts ...nd more parties negligent under comparative negligence?", International Review of Law and Economics 14, 21-34. Fluet, C. (1999), "Rйgulation des risques et insolvabilitй: le rфle de la responsabilitй pour faute en information imparfaite", Actualitй Йconomique 75, 379-400.
25 Fluet, C. (2003), "Enforcing contracts: should courts seek the truth?", Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 159, 49-69. Flanigan, G., Johnson, J., Winkle, D. and W. Ferguson (1989), "Experience from early tort reforms: comparative negligence since 1974", Journal of Risk and Insurance 56, 525-534. Hay, B. L. and K. E. Spier (1997), "Burdens of proof in civil litigation: an economic perspective", Journal of Legal Studies 26, 413-431. Hylton, K. N. (1990), "Costly litigation and legal error under negligence", Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization 6(2), 433-452. Kaplow, L. and S. Shavell (2002), "economic analysis and the law", in A.J. Auerbach and M Feldstein (eds.), Handbook of Public Economics, Vol. 3, North-Holland. Kessler, D. and M. McClellan (1996), "Do doctors practice defensive medicine?", Quarterly Journal of Economics 111, 353-390. Kim, S. K. (1995), "Eў ciency of an information system in an agency model", Econometrica 63, 89-102. Kolstad, C. D., T. S. Ulen and G. V. Johnson (1990), "Ex post liability for harm vs. ex ante safety regulation: substitutes or complements?", American Economic Review 80(4), 888-901. Landes, W. and R. Posner (1987), The Economic Structure of Tort Law, MA: Harvard University Press. Milgrom, P. (1981), "Good news and bad news: representation theorems and applications", Bell Journal of Economics 12, 380-391. Milgrom, P. and J. Roberts (1986), "Relying on the information of interested parties", Rand Journal of Economics 17, 18-32. Polinsky, M. A. and S. Shavell (1989), "Legal error, litigation , and the incentive to obey the law", Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 5, 99-108. Polinsky, A. M. and S. Shavell (1998), "Punitive damages: An economic analysis", Harvard Law Review 111, 869-962.
26 Rubinfeld, D. L. and D. E. Sappington (1987), "Eў cient awards and standards of proof in judicial proceedings", Rand Journal of Economics 18, 308-318. Sanchirico, C. W. (1997), "The burden of proof in civil litigation: a simple model of mechanism design", International Review of Law and Economics 17, 431-447. Schweizer, U. (2005), "Law and economics of obligations", International Review of Law and Economics 25, 209-228. Shavell, S. (1987), Economic Analysis of Accident Law, Harvard University Press, Harvard. White, M. J., (1989), "An empirical test of the comparative and contributory negligence rules in accident law", Rand Journal of Economics 20, 308-330.
- p'(u*) 0
b j(x)
a
F(x^, u*)
F(x0, u*)
F(x, u*) 1
Figure 1: Threshold under unilateral care
-(pvG + pGv) - pv
0b
b0
Figure 2: Threshold for victim
G 1
-(puF + pFu )(1-b )
-(puF + pFu )
- pu - pu(1-b )
0
a
a0
a' 1 F
Figure 3: Threshold for injurer

C Fluet

File: liability-rules-under-evidentiary-uncertainty.pdf
Author: C Fluet
Published: Wed Feb 15 15:27:47 2006
Pages: 30
File size: 0.33 Mb


Davis Guggenheim, 2 pages, 0.98 Mb

Why Study Medieval Folklore, 19 pages, 0.56 Mb

Naked mole rat gets dressed, 28 pages, 1.49 Mb
Copyright © 2018 doc.uments.com